The Moral Enigma of Shakespeare's Othello
From Hamlet, an ideal prince, and other essays in Shakesperean interpretation: Hamlet; Merchant of Venice; Othello; King Lear by Alexander W. Crawford. Boston R.G. Badger, 1916.
Few of the plays of Shakespeare have from the first excited more intense interest among both
theatre-goers and readers than the sad story of Othello and his life in Venice. The nature of the
Moor's difficulties and the deep pathos of his catastrophe have brought the play closer to the lives and bosoms of men than any other of the great tragedies. The general excellence of the character of Othello, the noble
Moor, and of Desdemona, the fair maid of Venice, together with the distressing nature of their marital conflict have made Othello the most heart-rending and the most moving of all the tragedies of Shakespeare. Many
persons who can observe with comparative calmness the awful conflict of aged father and ungrateful, ambitious daughters in King Lear are almost overcome by the appalling sadness of Othello's mistrust and murder of his young and beautiful wife. The passion of Othello seems more titanic, and the conflict more vital and elemental than that of King Lear. The ruin of filial
relationships seems less a tragedy than the overthrow and failure of the marital relationship, and the fate
that befalls Desdemona even less deserved than that which befalls Cordelia. Professor Bradley has truly
said, "There is no subject more exciting than sexual jealousy rising to the pitch of passion; and there can
hardly be any spectacle at once so engrossing and so painful as that of a great nature suffering the torment
of this passion, and driven by it to a crime which is also a hideous blunder."1
While all have been impressed by the deep and absorbing passion of the play, it has not always been for
the same reason. Shocked as all have been by the awful catastrophe, the real nature of the conflict and of the
outcome has been variously interpreted. The very intensity of the passion has doubtless confused our
notions, and sympathy and horror have often taken the place of careful study and clear thinking. Admiration
for the "noble Moor," compassion for the "divine Desdemona," and scorn for the intriguing Iago, have misguided our judgments, have obscured the story of the play and the very words that should reveal the true
character and actual deeds of the persons. In some cases both artistic sensibility and moral judgment have
been paralyzed, until Othello has become a perfect hero, Desdemona a spotless saint, and poor lago a
fiend incarnate. Instead of appreciating the play as it is written, and perceiving the informing thought of
the dramatist, this emotional criticism has made the injurer noble, his chief victim a saint, the injured a
devil, and Shakespeare foolish.
Othello has doubtless been very difficult of interpretation. More than half a century ago the Edinburgh
Review (1850) expressed only the truth when it said that "all critics of name have been perplexed by the
moral enigma which lies under this tragic tale." Since these words were written the opinion has become all but
universal that it is the moral aspects of the play that have made it difficult to understand. The passing
years, moreover, have forced the conviction upon many students that as the enigma of this play, and of many
others, is "moral," so the true interpretation must likewise be "moral." The solution of a play that is a
"moral enigma" must come if it comes at all from a solution of the moral aspects of the play, which can be
reached only by a due consideration of all the moral relations of the various persons of the drama. And
while it must be admitted that no expositions thus far have proven entirely satisfactory, the many earnest
attempts to unravel the "moral enigma" mark the only successes up to the present time that criticism has
made with this most fascinating drama.
There is no external source from which we can learn Shakespeare's dramatic purpose, and we can only infer
it as we see it unfolded in his plays. Like all the dramatists up to his time he let his plays speak for
themselves, and unlike many later dramatists he left no word of comment or explanation. The dedications
of Jonson, and the prefaces of Dryden and others have served to disclose their dramatic purposes and even to
interpret their dramas. But Shakespeare has left us no dedications and no prefaces. If he has revealed
anywhere his conception of the function of the drama it is in Hamlet's directions to the players, and these do
not help us in the interpretation of any particular play. Whether Shakespeare shared the opinion of
most other English dramatists and critics of his time that the drama should not only please but profit the
audience we cannot know directly. Three centuries of study have not yet made clear his attitude toward the principle of "poetic justice," as the moral aspects of the drama came later to be called. To this day the
discussion has gone on, and many students are inclined to think that in Othello and other plays he has ignored
this principle altogether. 2
In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries when criticism was almost entirely didactic, it was all but
unanimously agreed that Shakespeare paid no attention to moral subjects or to ethical forces. The burden of the critics from Rymer to Johnson was that Shakespeare had violated all our fundamental notions
of "poetic justice," or in other words had paid no attention whatsoever to moral considerations. In his
discussion of this subject Rymer chose Othello, as Professor Alden has recently said, "to show the extreme
results of neglecting this principle, on the part of the more or less barbarous Elizabethans. What unnatural
crime had Desdemona committed to bring such judgment upon her?" Rymer's own words are very strong:
"What instruction can be made out of this catastrophe? . . . How can it work, unless to delude our senses, disorder our thought, addle our brain, pervert our affections, corrupt our appetite, and fill our head
with vanity, confusion, tintamarre, and jingle-jangle?"3 The same opinion was still held in the time of
Dr. Johnson, nearly a century later. In the preface to his edition of Shakespeare Johnson says: "His first
defect is that ... he sacrifices virtue to convenience, is so much more careful to please than to instruct,
hat he seems to write without any moral purpose . . . he makes no just distribution of good and evil, nor is
always careful to show in the virtuous a disapprobation of the wicked. . . ."
These critics are in substantial agreement with all other English criticism, whether applied directly to
Shakespeare or not, in their demand that the drama should not violate our fundamental moral notions. The
history of the principle of "poetic justice" in English criticism shows that English thought has always applied itself to the more ethical phases of the drama, but we shall find that the classical and formal conceptions of the principle held in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries were hopelessly inadequate for the living and romantic Elizabethan drama. The criticism as well as the drama of that period falls far short of dealing adequately with large and living conceptions,
and when they attempted to interpret Shakespeare their limitations became very apparent. The classical period was utterly unable to deal with any dramatist at once so large and so vital as Shakespeare.
In the nineteenth century there arose a generation of romantic critics who knew not the classicists of the
ages of Rymer and Johnson. These equally with the earlier critics demanded that Shakespeare should
square himself with our moral conceptions, but they had outlived the formalism of their predecessors and
had learned to look in other places for Shakespeare's "poetic justice." Actuated with the stubborn notion
that his moral conceptions were not to be found in explicit utterance, or in didactic phrase, they began to
look for an implicit morality in the construction and conduct of the narratives of the plays, and in so doing
opened up the most fruitful of all eras of Shakespeare study.
The first, of this long line of able critics was Coleridge, with whom as a recent writer has said, "Rational
appreciation may be said to begin in England." It was a vast step forward in criticism when this great
man, poet and critic in one, laid aside the idea that Shakespeare was in need either of revision or criticism,
and inaugurated the modern attempt at interpretation. Though succeeding ages have found plenty of reason
for dissenting from many of his opinions we have never really departed from his method of interpretation.
In his study of Othello, as of other plays, Coleridge made a diligent search for the dramatic motive, and
tried to find out the underlying reason for the catastrophe that had puzzled earlier critics. Instead of trying
to show defects in Shakespeare's notions of poetic justice, he attempted to find the reason if not the justification for the catastrophe. Carefully surveying the play, he reached the conviction that in Othello Shakespeare was portraying a man whose misfortunes were due to the intrigue of another, and were not intended by the dramatist to appear as retribution for any of his own misdeeds. In Iago and his evil mind Coleridge found the sole cause of Othello's tragic end. To Iago's
"motiveless malignity"3 must be ascribed, he says, the entire catastrophe. This man is "a being next to devil,
and only not quite devil."4 It is his evil and jealous mind that works all the harm done to Othello and his
wife.
From this it is clear at any rate that Coleridge saw the importance of a right understanding of the relations of Othello and Iago for a proper comprehension and interpretation of the play. It will appear, however, as we proceed that Coleridge overlooked some of the most important factors in the relations of these two, and that he had not shaken off entirely the eighteenth century habit of trying to form our own opinion of Shakespeare's characters, instead of ascertaining
the dramatist's opinion. It is of course permissible for any one to differ from the dramatist about any of
his characters, but it is not permissible to substitute this opinion for the dramatist's, and then on this basis
charge the dramatist with being inartistic or with a violation of our moral principles. Even less satisfactory, however, is Coleridge's treatment of the relations of Othello and Desdemona, a proper understanding of
which is all but as important as that of Othello and Iago. This also will call for the most careful study.
But, though Coleridge's treatment of these two topics has not settled the interpretation of the play, it can
be freely maintained that the method he adopted is the only hopeful method for the interpretation of the
drama.
Continue to Part 2: Othello as Tragic Hero
________
FOOTNOTE 1: Shakespearean Tragedy, pp. 177-8. London, 2nd edition, 1905.
FOOTNOTE 2: Of. Professor R. M. Alden, The Decline of Poetic Justice, Atlantic Monthly, February, 1910, pp. 260-7.
FOOTNOTE 3: Johnson, Shakespeare and His Critics, p. 18 ; Houghton, Mifflin
& Co., 1909.
FOOTNOTE 4: Lectures on Shakespeare (Bonn's Library), p. 388.
How to cite this article:
Crawford, Alexander W. Hamlet, an ideal prince, and other essays in Shakesperean interpretation: Hamlet; Merchant of Venice; Othello; King Lear. Boston R.G. Badger, 1916. Shakespeare Online. 20 Aug. 2009. (date when you accessed the information) < http://www.shakespeare-online.com/plays/othello/othellobradley2.html >.
_________
Related Articles
How to Pronounce the Names in Othello
Stage History of Othello
Othello: Plot Summary
Othello: Q & A
Quotes from Othello
Iago Character Introduction
Othello Character Introduction
Desdemona Character Introduction
Othello: Essay Topics
Shakespeare's Sources for Othello
The Problem of Time in Othello
|
|